Thursday 31 December 2020

Fawcett On Classes Of Clause

Fawcett (2010: 201, 201n):
We have noted that, in the "Categories" framework, there is a 'unit' on the 'rank scale' called the "clause". From the 'rank scale' viewpoint it is surely odd that, unlike the 'rank scale units' of 'group' and "word', there is only one class of the "clause", namely the clause. Yet this fact is never commented on.⁷ 
⁷ Clauses can of course be classified in terms of the features in the network that generates them, e.g., as 'independent' or 'dependent' clauses, and as 'action' or 'mental' or 'relational' clauses — but this should not lead one to set up "classes of clause". These differences are quite unlike the distinction between a nominal group and a prepositional group; rather, they are like the distinction between a nominal group that has a modifier and one without one — i.e., they are different from each other, but they are still the same 'class of unit'. If a grammar did set up 'classes of clause' along these lines, there would be as many different classes of clause as there are combinations of semantic features realised in the clause — i.e., millions of millions. Surprisingly, Matthiessen (1995:77) describes the following as "grammatical classes" of clause: 'major' and 'minor' clauses and, within 'major clauses', 'free' and 'bound' clauses. Yet these are simply early features in the sub-network for the clause.


Blogger Comments:

[1] This is misleading. As Fawcett knows, since he has been arguing against it, Halliday classifies units in terms of the functions they serve at a higher rank. Halliday (2002 [1963]: 95-7):

I have assumed, for the purpose of the main points made in the paper, that this category of “class” is to be defined syntactically. By this I mean that the concept is introduced into the description of a language in order to bring together those sets of items that have the same potentiality of occurrence; in other words, sets of items which are alike in the way they pattern in the structure of items of higher rank. 

Clearly, since the clause is the highest ranked unit, it cannot be classified in terms of its functions at a higher rank.

[2] This is not misleading, because it is true. In treating 'major' and 'minor' as classes of clause, Matthiessen (1995: 77-8) is inconsistent with the criteria that Halliday uses to distinguish classes of unit in SFL Theory. Instead of using the scale of rank, Matthiessen has used the scale of delicacy to classify the clause by its features.

In 201 pages, this is Fawcett's first valid critique. Happy New Year!

Tuesday 29 December 2020

Theoretical Problems With Fawcett's Model Of Clause Structure

 Fawcett (2010: 200-1):

The most frequent elements of the English clause are the Subject, Operator and Main Verb, with one or more Complements and potentially many Adjuncts, selected from over forty functionally differentiated types. Typically, a Participant Role (such as Agent, Affected, Carrier or Attribute) is conflated with the Subject or Complement. Auxiliary Verbs and Main Verb Extensions also occur frequently, as do the Binders and Linkers that relate the clause out to another unit. See Appendix B and Fawcett (in press) for a fuller picture, including six other elements.


Blogger Comments:

[1] To be clear, on Fawcett's model, Figure 4 (p36), structure is located at the level of form:

Inconsistent with this, Fawcett's elements of structure are a confusion of form (Main Verb) and function (Subject, Operator, Complement, Adjunct). In SFL Theory, these functions are interpersonal functions.

[2] To be clear, Fawcett locates Halliday's systems of the clause at his level of meaning. In such a formulation, the participant rôles of Agent, Affected, Carrier, Attribute etc. (meaning) and the structural elements Subject and Complement (form) are located at different levels of symbolic abstraction. On this model, therefore, participant rôles are not conflated with Subject and Complement, but are realised by them, since realisation is the relation between levels of symbolic abstraction. That is, what Fawcett actually proposes is that experiential meanings are realised by elements of syntactic structure that correspond to interpersonal wordings in SFL Theory.

Sunday 27 December 2020

The 'Clause' In The Cardiff Grammar

Fawcett (2010: 200):
The unit of the 'clause' is almost certainly central in every human language. It is the syntactic unit that corresponds to the semantic unit of the situation — and so typically, as we shall shortly see, to the unit of event in the belief system. A clause has the syntax potential that it does because of the particularly rich and complex array of meanings that we wish to express to each other about 'events'. However, a clause occasionally refers to an object that is identified by its role in an event, as in what I ate; see Section 10.2.9 below.


Blogger Comments:

[1] To be clear, in Fawcett's model, as represented in Figure 12 (p210 and below), there is only ideational meaning — no interpersonal or textual meaning — and these meanings of language are additionally reconstrued as meanings outside language, in a belief system: situation as event, and thing as object.

A single metafunction model and a higher level belief system are both inconsistent with SFL Theory. On the latter point, Halliday & Matthiessen (1999: 3) write:

We contend that the conception of 'knowledge' as something that exists independently of language, and may then be coded or made manifest in language, is illusory.

[2] To be clear, the clause is not limited to expressing ideational meaning, and its semogenic potential lies in being the rank unit onto which all metafunctions can be mapped structurally. Halliday & Matthiessen (2014: 10):

The clause is the central processing unit in the lexicogrammar – in the specific sense that it is in the clause that meanings of different kinds are mapped into an integrated grammatical structure.

Thursday 24 December 2020

The Advantage Of Using Fawcett's Criteria For Classifying Units

Fawcett (2010: 200):
One notable fact about most published description of English using SFL is that the accounts given of the groups are very much less full than those of the clause. It therefore seems possible that in a future revision of IFG Halliday may take to its logical conclusion the change in criteria signalled in Halliday (1963). As one indication of the advantage of changing, consider the fact that, in Halliday's current approach there can be no equivalent of the useful summary of English syntax given in Appendix B, because generalisations based on the internal structure of units have little or no place in his theory of syntax.


Blogger Comments:

[1] To be clear, the focus on the clause in SFL Theory arises from the sense in which the clause is the 'central processing unit' of the grammar. Halliday & Matthiessen (2014: 10):

The clause is the central processing unit in the lexicogrammar – in the specific sense that it is in the clause that meanings of different kinds are mapped into an integrated grammatical structure. For this reason the first half of this book is organised around the principal systems of the clause: theme, mood and transitivity.

[2] This is misleading. As previously demonstrated, Halliday (1963) outlines these alternative criteria for classifying units, which Fawcett uses, before making clear that these are the criteria that he does not take up. Such a conclusion would, therefore, be far from logical.

[3] To be clear, the theoretical advantage of using Fawcett's criteria for classifying units is being able to use his criteria to classify units, whose tree structures are usefully summarised in Appendix B. This is an instance of the logical fallacy known as circular reasoning.

[4] This not misleading, because it is true.

[5] This is misleading. As previously explained, Halliday's SFL Theory is not a theory of syntax. Halliday (1985 & 1994: xiv):

Tuesday 22 December 2020

Presenting Bare Assertions As Supporting Argument: Butler, Huddleston And Hudson

Fawcett (2010: 199-200):
Butler, in his useful discussion of this issue, is quite clear about what the answer should be. He points out that "if we are to account for the variety of structures available in a language, we shall have to elevate structural type to a more central position in the theory than Halliday suggests" (Butler 1985:34). And, referring to two papers by Halliday's two closest colleagues in the 1960s (Huddleston 1966/81 and Hudson 1967/81) he goes on to say that: "although neither [...] actually defines class, their discussion suggests that their criteria for classification are those of internal constituency".
It therefore seems that there is a basic difference here between, on the one hand, Halliday and those whose publications have been written with the goal of expounding and complementing IFG, and on the other hand almost all other grammarians who have worked on the analysis of English using SFL.


Blogger Comments:

[1] To be clear, the claim by Fawcett's supporter, Butler, is merely a bare assertion, unsupported by any argument as to why accounting for the variety of structures requires elevating structural type to a more central position in Systemic Theory. As the name suggests, Systemic Theory is concerned with modelling language as system, not structure, and structures are specified in the system through realisation statements. Halliday (1995[1993]: 272):

In systemic theory the system takes priority; the most abstract representation at any level is in paradigmatic terms. Syntagmatic organisation is interpreted as the 'realisation' of paradigmatic features.

[2] To be clear, what the 1960s work of two non-Systemicists, Huddleston and Hudson, suggests to Butler is not argument as to why classifying units according to their internal structure has more explanatory potential than classifying them according to the function they realise. That is, this is another instance of the logical fallacy known as argumentum ab auctoritate, whereby authorities are cited instead of their arguments.

Moreover, to take the view 'from below' on this matter creates a theoretical inconsistency in a theory that gives priority to the view 'from above': system over structure, function over form.

[3] This is misleading, not least because Butler, Fawcett, Huddleston (1966) and Hudson (1967) come nowhere near constituting "almost all other grammarians who have worked on the analysis of English using SFL". Moreover, this is an attempt to deploy the logical fallacy known as argumentum ad populum.

Sunday 20 December 2020

Presenting Bare Assertions As Supporting Argument: Sinclair

Fawcett (2010: 199):
Sinclair, who was one of Halliday's closest colleagues at the time, published in 1972 an introduction to systemic grammar in which he included all of the following as criteria for recognising units:
a) the guidance given by similar or different meanings (i.e., semantic criteria); 
b) the internal details or componence of structure; 
c) the external details, or syntax of structures. (Sinclair 1972:23)
Since the second and third criteria are often in conflict, this list should perhaps be taken as an indication of the order of Sinclair's preferences — and we note that Halliday's standard criterion is relegated to third place. In the present theory we go one step further, as in Fawcett (1974-6/81:10), and exclude the last criterion altogether. Sinclair does not explain what he intends by "semantic criteria", but at the very least his wording allows for the possibility that semantics influences syntax in the way described at the start of Section 10.2.1.


Blogger Comments:

[1] To be clear, Sinclair's criteria, from 1972, are not supported by reasoned argument.

[2] To be clear, as previously demonstrated, the criteria that Fawcett rejects, (c), are the those that take the view 'from above', and so are consistent with SFL as a functional theory, whereas the criteria that Fawcett accepts, (b), are those that take the view 'from below', and so are inconsistent with SFL as a functional theory.

[3] To be clear, in SFL Theory, semantics does not "influence" syntax, semantics is realised by lexicogrammar. That is, they are in a relation of intensive identity, as two levels of symbolic abstraction, Value and Token, having originated as one, and dissociated in grammatical metaphor (Halliday & Matthiessen 1999: 26).

Friday 18 December 2020

Misrepresenting Halliday (1963) On Class

Fawcett (2010: 199):
So far as I am aware, Halliday has never shown why facts such as those described above are not counter-examples to his claim. However, he has commented in an interesting manner on a partly similar set of examples in Halliday (1963/76). Here he addresses the fact that a nominal group such as this morning functions as an Adjunct just as naturally as it functions as a Subject or Complement (and far more frequently). Here he reaches the conclusion that
this morning "clearly resembles other nominal groups (the morning, this man, etc.) rather than other adverbial groups (quickly, on the floor, etc.) and this can be allowed to determine its primary syntactic assignment [my emphasis]. (Halliday 1963:6)
How does this acknowledgement of the facts affect his view of the criteria for recognising units? The answer is that it appears to remain unchanged, on the evidence of the criteria used for recognising units in IFG. But if the criterion of the internal structure applies in the above case, one asks, why not in all cases?


Blogger Comments:

[1] To be clear, as the previous post demonstrates, these "facts" are misunderstandings on Fawcett's part, and so do not constitute counter-examples to the criteria used in SFL Theory for classifying units.

[2] This is very misleading indeed. As demonstrated in a previous post, this highly selective excerpt from Halliday (1963) is concerned with explaining the alternative criteria for classifying units that, unlike Fawcett, he himself does not adopt. Halliday (2002 [1963]: 95-7):
I have assumed, for the purpose of the main points made in the paper, that this category of “class” is to be defined syntactically. By this I mean that the concept is introduced into the description of a language in order to bring together those sets of items that have the same potentiality of occurrence; in other words, sets of items which are alike in the way they pattern in the structure of items of higher rank. Thus, to take a typical instance from grammar, we may have morpheme classes defined by word structure, each such class being one set of morphemes having a given value in the structure of words: as, for example, the morphemes of inflexion in Latin nouns. Likewise we might have word–classes defined by group structure, or clause–classes by sentence structure.
This use of the term “class”, to name a category defined in some way by its relationship to a higher structure, is by no means universal in linguistics; but it would probably be granted that some such category is necessary to linguistic description whatever name we choose to adopt for it. Syntactic classification (sometimes referred to as “functional classification”, in what is perhaps a rather misleading opposition of “form” and “function”) is a central feature of linguistic method, and one which it seems appropriate to discuss in the present context.
The alternative to this use of the term “class” is to consider morphological classification. Here “class” would be the name given to a set of items which are alike in their own structure: that is, in the way that they themselves are made up of items of lower rank. A word–class would then be a set of words having a certain similarity in their own formation out of morphemes. In this usage there are no morpheme classes, since “morpheme” is the name given to the smallest unit in grammar, which by definition has no structure: its relation to items abstracted at other levels, such as phonemes, is not one of structure, but involves the interrelation of different dimensions of abstraction.
It is important to notice that this is in the first instance a terminological alternative, not necessarily implying a different theory. It is not the case that the linguist has to choose between two different kinds of classification, the syntactic and the morphological; he has in fact to recognise both kinds of likeness. Moreover, the sets of items identified on these two criteria often coincide: we may recognize a syntactic class “noun”, for example, defined as “that class of word which operates as head of a nominal group”, and find that the items grouped together on this criterion will be the same set as would be grouped together on a morphological criterion such as “that type of word which is made up of a stem morpheme followed by a morpheme of case and a morpheme of number”.1 Indeed other things being equal, it is usually accepted as desirable that the two should coincide: when the linguist is faced, as he often is, with a choice between two descriptions, both theoretically valid and both accounting for the facts, one in which the two assignments coincide and one in which they do not, he will normally, and “intuitively”, choose the former. For example, groups in English such as this morning operate in clause structure both as Adjunct, as in “I came this morning”, and as Subject (or Complement), as in “this morning promises to be fine” (or “I’ve set this morning aside for it”). The syntactic class defined by operation as Adjunct is the adverbial group; that defined by operation as Subject or Complement is the nominal group. Syntactically, therefore, this morning could be assigned to either or both of these classes. Morphologically, however, it clearly resembles other nominal groups (the morning, this man, etc.) rather than other adverbial groups (quickly, on the floor, etc.), and this can be allowed to determine its primary syntactic assignment.
There are, however, clear instances where syntactically defined sets do not coincide with morphologically defined sets; and it would probably be generally agreed that, whatever the status accorded to the latter, the former cannot be ignored. Syntactic likeness must be accounted for. Moreover, even where the two sets do coincide, the criteria on which they have been established, and therefore their theoretical status, is different; and it is desirable that they should not be called by the same name. It seems to me appropriate that the term “class” should be reserved for the syntactic set (the morphological set may then be referred to as a “type”), and I propose to adopt this usage here. It is also true, in my opinion, that the class thus defined, the syntactic set, is crucial to the whole of linguistic theory, since it is required to give meaning to the basic concepts of “structure” and “system”; whereas the type, or morphological set, is more a descriptive convenience whose theoretical implications are largely internal to itself.
In the remaining sections of this paper, therefore, I should like to discuss two aspects of the syntactically defined set, which I shall refer to henceforward simply as the “class”.

Tuesday 15 December 2020

Problems With Fawcett's Critique Of Halliday's Criterion For Classifying Groups

Fawcett (2010: 198-9):
What reasons could Halliday have had for setting up classes of unit on the basis of their potential for operation in the unit above? The most likely is the generalisation that nominal groups tend to occur as the Subjects and Complements of clauses. 
The first problem for his criterion is the fact that nominal groups also occur very frequently as elements of other unitsparticularly in prepositional groups. Such cases challenge his criterion, because it requires the higher unit to be 'above' the current unit on the 'rank scale', and in such cases it is at the same 'rank'. 
A second problem for Halliday's criterion, as Butler points out (1985:33), is the fact that an expression such as very clever is classified by Halliday as a type of "nominal group". The problem is that, although it occurs naturally as a Complement, it does not occur (except in quotation marks) as a Subject. It is therefore a counter-example to the claim that nominal groups are defined by their potential to operate as both Subject and Complement. While Halliday himself points out this inconsistency (IFG p. 80), the fact that he does so does not weaken its force as an argument against his general claim. 
And the problems for his claim increase when we also take into account the fact that a unit such as very clever can also function as the modifier in a nominal group (e.g., a very clever cat). Is it still a nominal group in such a case, in IFG terms? It appears not, since on p. 192 it is analysed as a case of "submodification". But there is no explanation of this inconsistency. 
These facts present no problem for the model outlined here, because it assumes that it is a natural characteristic of language that two units with the same internal structure should be able to fill two or more elements of other units (as is demonstrated in the summary of what units can fill what elements in Appendix B).


Blogger Comments:

[1] To be clear, Halliday's criterion derives from the functional perspective of taking the view 'from above', and from the broader notion that a functional grammar incorporates the natural relation between semantics and grammatical form, as between participant and noun (expanded as nominal group), and between process and verb (expanded as verbal group). Halliday (1994: xviii):


Halliday & Matthiessen (2014:363) relate group and phrase classes to both the experiential and modal structures of the clause:

[2] To be clear, Fawcett here takes the view 'from below' (nominal group) instead of the (SFL) view 'from above' (clause function). The question is whether nominal groups are distinguished from other groups in that they congruently realise Subject, Complement or a participant rôle.

[3] To be clear, in SFL Theory, nominal groups do not "occur as elements of prepositional groups". Nominal groups are constituents of prepositional phrases, and they realise the Complement/Range element of phrase structure. Where a group is an expanded word, a phrase is a contracted clause, with its preposition serving as minor Process/Predicator. The reason why group and phrase are located at the same point on the rank scale, is that both realise clause rank functions. On Halliday's model, it is the prepositional phrase that realises a clause rank function — Adjunct/circumstance rôle — not its constituent nominal group.

[4] To be clear, Butler makes the same error as Fawcett, in taking the view 'from below' (nominal group) instead of the (SFL) view 'from above' (clause function). The question is whether nominal groups are distinguished from other groups in that they congruently realise Subject, Complement or a participant rôle. It is because Attributes/Complements are realised by groups like very clever, over sixty, a slow learner that all three variants can be classified as nominal groups.

[5] This is misleading. The exceptionality here is the fact that the functions of Attribute and Subject cannot conflate. Halliday (1994: 80):

[6] To be clear, there is no inconsistency here. Here again Fawcett takes the view 'from below' (form) instead of the (SFL) view 'from above' (function). The wording very clever as in a very clever cat is a unit in Fawcett's Cardiff Grammar, but not in SFL Theory. In SFL theory, the unit is a very clever cat, a nominal group, and identified as such by the fact that, like other nominal groups, it congruently realises Subject, Complement and participant rôles of clause rank structures.

[7] To be clear, on the one hand, these are not "facts"; see [2] to [6] above. On the other hand, the view 'from above' does not rule out the possibility "that two units with the same internal structure should be able to fill two or more elements of other units" as demonstrated by the fact that a prepositional phrase can serve in either a circumstantial or participant rôle at clause rank:

Sunday 13 December 2020

Why Fawcett Rejects Halliday's Criteria For Classes Of Unit

Fawcett (2010: 197-8):
There is a crucial difference, therefore, between the theoretical positions taken on this matter in the Sydney and the Cardiff Grammars. Moreover, there are many other systemic linguists who have differed from Halliday on this key matter, as we shall now see.
Butler (1985:33-5) provides a valuable discussion of several of the problems with Halliday's concept of 'class', referring to some of the key contributions to the literature that it has generated. He points out that "certain other systemicists" — including Huddleston (1966/81), Hudson (1967/81) and myself (Fawcett 1974-6/81) — had by then abandoned Halliday's criterion of the potential for operation in the unit above it on the 'rank scale', in favour of the criterion of "the internal structure of units".
This leads to the question of why I and others should have abandoned this central tenet of Halliday's theory. My own answer — and I cannot speak for Huddleston and Hudson — is that my experience of building models of English syntax (for use in both generating and describing text) has taught me that the model become [sic] far more insightful, when I treat the internal structural patterns of a unit as the defining ones (for the reasons given in Section 10.2.1). One must operate with either internal criteria or external criteria (the latter being operation in the unit next above on the 'rank scale'), because the two are often in conflict. I find that the descriptive facts of natural texts in English and other languages provide just too many clear examples where it distorts the facts to categorise them in terms of their operation in a higher unit, and where it is insightful to categorise them in terms of their internal syntactic-semantic structure.


Blogger Comments:

[1] This is misleading. On the one hand, the "many" systemic linguists are four in number, namely:

  • Fawcett himself,
  • Christopher Butler, an advocate of Fawcett's Cardiff Grammar,
  • Richard Hudson, who was Halliday's research assistant (1964-70) and is not a systemic linguist (his theory is 'Word Grammar'), and
  • Rodney Huddleston, who was Halliday's student (1961-3) and research assistant (1964-7), and is not a systemic linguist.
On the other hand, here Fawcett combines the logical fallacy known as argumentum ad populum ('many other systemic linguists') with the logical fallacy known as argumentum ab auctoritate, whereby authorities are cited instead of their arguments.

[2] To be clear, Fawcett does not provide any reasoned arguments from Butler (1985: 33-5) as to why Hudson and Huddleston see Halliday's concept of 'class' as problematic.

[3] To be clear, this is but bare assertion ("far more insightful") unsupported by reasoned argument.

[4] This is misleading. As previously demonstrated, Fawcett's Section 10.2.1 merely outlines, in general terms, the concept of 'class of unit' in the Cardiff Grammar. It does not provide any reasons as to why classifying units on the basis of structure is "far more insightful".

[5] To be clear, in SFL Theory, this corresponds to taking the view 'from below' ("internal criteria") or the view 'from above' ("external criteria"). In Systemic Functional Linguistics priority is given to the view 'from above': to system over structure, to function over form. Fawcett's view is inconsistent with the principles of SFL Theory.

[6] To be clear, if the two are often in conflict, then the conflict is between taking Halliday's systemic-functional perspective and taking Fawcett's structural-formal perspective.

[7] To be clear, this is another bare assertion unsupported by reasoned argument.

[8] This is misleading, because it is untrue. In Fawcett's model, Figure 4 (p36), structure is syntactic (formal), but not semantic (meaning):

Friday 11 December 2020

Misrepresenting Fawcett On Class Of Unit

Fawcett (2010: 197):
Halliday takes a very different approach to the criteria for recognising a 'class of unit'. While the criterion used here is the unit's internal structure (together with semantic criteria, as described in Section 10.2.1), for Halliday the criterion is the unit's ability to fill elements of units at the 'rank' next above it on the 'rank scale' (as we saw in Section 2.3 of Chapter 2). Thus Halliday's definition of 'class of unit' is dependent — like so much else in his theory — on the concept of the 'rank scale'.
It is interesting to note that Halliday later (1963/76) introduced to the theory a concept that he termed "type". It was introduced as a complement to 'class', in a sense that is exactly equivalent to the concept of 'class of unit' as it is used here. In other words, in Halliday (1963/76) a unit's 'type' is defined in terms of a unit's internal structure. Interestingly, while Berry's introduction to the theory gives a clear account of the difference between this concept and Halliday's "Categories" sense of 'class of unit' (1975:76-7, 124-6), Berry makes no further use of it, and the concept has not been used in most later accounts of the theory. Thus it is not mentioned by Halliday in either "Systemic theory" or IFG, nor by Matthiessen (1995). 
Moreover, in both IFG and Matthiessen (1995) units continue to be defined in the "Categories" manner. Halliday is clearly using this criterion when deciding to treat very lucky in You're very lucky as a nominal group (p. 194 of IFG), and Matthiessen emphasises the correlation between "grammatical units of different classes" and their "functional potential [in the unit above]" (Matthiessen 1995:22).


Blogger Comments:

[1] To be clear, this is not misleading, because it is true.

[2] To be clear, this is misleading, because it is untrue. As previously demonstrated, Fawcett's classifies his units differently according to the syntagmatic structure of each unit ('from below'), not on the basis of the meaning it realises ('from above'). For example, as previously discussed, he classifies the groups over sixty and very clever differently — as quantity vs quality group — despite the fact that both congruently realise the same meaning: Attribute.

[3] To be clear, this is slightly misleading. It is not so much that the 'definition' of class of unit is dependent on a rank scale, but that the rank scale provides a grammatical means of modelling the natural relation between meaning (e.g. thing) and grammatical form (e.g. noun). See, for example, Halliday & Matthiessen (1999: 15, 18ff).

[4] This is very misleading indeed. Halliday (1963) only outlines this alternative method in order to identify it as the approach he is not taking — which is why it is not taken up later by Berry, Halliday or Matthiessen. Halliday (2002 [1963]: 95-7):

I have assumed, for the purpose of the main points made in the paper, that this category of “class” is to be defined syntactically. By this I mean that the concept is introduced into the description of a language in order to bring together those sets of items that have the same potentiality of occurrence; in other words, sets of items which are alike in the way they pattern in the structure of items of higher rank. Thus, to take a typical instance from grammar, we may have morpheme classes defined by word structure, each such class being one set of morphemes having a given value in the structure of words: as, for example, the morphemes of inflexion in Latin nouns. Likewise we might have word–classes defined by group structure, or clause–classes by sentence structure.
This use of the term “class”, to name a category defined in some way by its relationship to a higher structure, is by no means universal in linguistics; but it would probably be granted that some such category is necessary to linguistic description whatever name we choose to adopt for it. Syntactic classification (sometimes referred to as “functional classification”, in what is perhaps a rather misleading opposition of “form” and “function”) is a central feature of linguistic method, and one which it seems appropriate to discuss in the present context.
The alternative to this use of the term “class” is to consider morphological classification. Here “class” would be the name given to a set of items which are alike in their own structure: that is, in the way that they themselves are made up of items of lower rank. A word–class would then be a set of words having a certain similarity in their own formation out of morphemes. In this usage there are no morpheme classes, since “morpheme” is the name given to the smallest unit in grammar, which by definition has no structure: its relation to items abstracted at other levels, such as phonemes, is not one of structure, but involves the interrelation of different dimensions of abstraction.
It is important to notice that this is in the first instance a terminological alternative, not necessarily implying a different theory. It is not the case that the linguist has to choose between two different kinds of classification, the syntactic and the morphological; he has in fact to recognise both kinds of likeness. Moreover, the sets of items identified on these two criteria often coincide: we may recognise a syntactic class “noun”, for example, defined as “that class of word which operates as head of a nominal group”, and find that the items grouped together on this criterion will be the same set as would be grouped together on a morphological criterion such as “that type of word which is made up of a stem morpheme followed by a morpheme of case and a morpheme of number”. Indeed other things being equal, it is usually accepted as desirable that the two should coincide: when the linguist is faced, as he often is, with a choice between two descriptions, both theoretically valid and both accounting for the facts, one in which the two assignments coincide and one in which they do not, he will normally, and “intuitively”, choose the former. For example, groups in English such as this morning operate in clause structure both as Adjunct, as in “I came this morning”, and as Subject (or Complement), as in “this morning promises to be fine” (or “I’ve set this morning aside for it”). The syntactic class defined by operation as Adjunct is the adverbial group; that defined by operation as Subject or Complement is the nominal group. Syntactically, therefore, this morning could be assigned to either or both of these classes. Morphologically, however, it clearly resembles other nominal groups (the morning, this man, etc.) rather than other adverbial groups (quickly, on the floor, etc.), and this can be allowed to determine its primary syntactic assignment.
There are, however, clear instances where syntactically defined sets do not coincide with morphologically defined sets; and it would probably be generally agreed that, whatever the status accorded to the latter, the former cannot be ignored. Syntactic likeness must be accounted for. Moreover, even where the two sets do coincide, the criteria on which they have been established, and therefore their theoretical status, is different; and it is desirable that they should not be called by the same name. It seems to me appropriate that the term “class” should be reserved for the syntactic set (the morphological set may then be referred to as a “type”), and I propose to adopt this usage here. It is also true, in my opinion, that the class thus defined, the syntactic set, is crucial to the whole of linguistic theory, since it is required to give meaning to the basic concepts of “structure” and “system”; whereas the type, or morphological set, is more a descriptive convenience whose theoretical implications are largely internal to itself.
In the remaining sections of this paper, therefore, I should like to discuss two aspects of the syntactically defined set, which I shall refer to henceforward simply as the “class”.

Tuesday 8 December 2020

Fawcett's Notion Of 'Conceptual' Representations In A Belief System

Fawcett (2010: 196-7):
In the present theory, then, the decision to recognise a possible class of unit is dependent on the recognition of the semantic similarities between configurations of functionally motivated elements, based on the comparison of large numbers of instances in texts of potential members of that unit. However, we should also note that it is not the case that a syntactic unit always corresponds in a one-to-one manner to the event or object etc. to which it refers, i.e., to its equivalent 'conceptual' representation in the belief system. In a slowly evolving construct such as a natural human language (as opposed to an artificial language such as a logic) we should expect to find quite frequent cases of the lack of a one-to-one fit of this type. (For some typical cases such as that of 'nominalisation', see Section 10.2.10.)


Blogger Comments:

[1] This is misleading. Fawcett classifies units by their structural similarities ('from below'). In Fawcett's model (Figure 4), such structures are syntactic, not semantic.

[2] To be clear, Fawcett here refers to the model given in Figure 12 (p210):


As can be seen, Fawcett's model reduces all meaning to ideational meaning, and reinstates the meanings of language (event, object) outside language. This is fundamentally inconsistent with the epistemological assumptions on which SFL Theory has been constructed. Halliday & Matthiessen (1999: 2-3):

In modelling the meaning base [i.e. ideational semantics] we are building it 'upwards' from the grammar, instead of working 'downwards' from some interpretation of experience couched in conceptual terms, and seen as independent of language. We contend that the conception of 'knowledge' as something that exists independently of language, and may then be coded or made manifest in language, is illusory.

Sunday 6 December 2020

Confusing Experiential With Logical Structure And Misconstruing Form As Function

Fawcett (2010: 196):
In many theories of syntax there is an assumption that each unit has an element that is obligatorily present (often called the 'head'). This reflects the traditional assumption that a unit is essentially the 'expansion' of a word — a concept which is replaced here by recognising the fact that each element realises one aspect of the unit's meaning, as explained in Section 10.2.1. But among formal grammarians — i.e., those who are influenced by formal language theory (i.e., the theory of 'formal' languages) — there is a tendency to transfer the characteristics of formal languages to natural languages, and so to construct theories for parsing natural languages on the basis of such assumptions (e.g., 'head-driven parsers'). However, the data of natural language texts suggest that such concepts express strong tendencies rather than absolute rules.
On the other hand, the concept of an element that is typically present in a given class of unit is useful (e.g., when the theory of syntax is to be used by a parser), and on those occasions when we need to refer to such an element we shall call it, informally, the pivotal element of the unit. Examples of nominal groups that have no heads include the very rich and five in Give me five (see Fawcett in press for the reasons for these analyses). And for a discussion of the Main Verb as the pivotal element of the clause, see Section 10.4.2.


Blogger Comments:

[1] To be clear, Fawcett's claims here are that

  • his model replaces logical structure with experiential structure, and
  • only experiential structure "recognises the fact that each element realises one aspect of the unit's meaning".
On the first claim, it will be demonstrated that Fawcett confuses logical and experiential structure; see below. On the second claim, logical structure construes meaning in terms of the relation of modification, which thus also "recognises the fact that each element realises one aspect of the unit's meaning".

[2] To be clear, the structural element that is "typically" present is the Head, since this is the element that is optionally modified. That is, on the one hand, Fawcett rejects logical structure, while on the other, he uses one of its elements, the Head, and renames it the Pivot.

[3] To be clear, these nominal groups do have Head elements (logical structure); what they do not have are Thing elements (experiential structure). That is, Fawcett's model confuses logical and experiential structure.


[4] To be clear, 'Fawcett in press' (Functional Syntax Handbook) is still unpublished, 20 years after the first edition of this book.

[5] To be clear, on the one hand, this unwittingly construes the clause as a logical structure, since 'Pivot' is demonstrably Fawcett's term for 'Head'; see above. On the other hand, it misconstrues a class of form (main verb) as an element of function structure.

Friday 4 December 2020

Classifying Groups By Their Internal Structure

Fawcett (2010: 196n):
⁶ Let me give an example of the use of these criteria when introducing a new class of unit. The quantity group was only introduced to the present description of English syntax when detailed studies of this area of the grammar showed that it could not reasonably be handled in terms of an existing unit, such as the quality group. In other words, it became clear that there are units with 'quantities' as their pivotal element (e.g., over sixty) as well as groups with 'qualities' as their pivotal element (e.g., quite clever) — and that the elements of structure in the two classes of unit serve different functions. 


Blogger Comments:

[1] To be clear, for Fawcett (p196):
… the different classes of syntactic unit that are recognised in the description of a language are to be identified by their internal structure, i.e., by the elements of structure of those units.
[2] To be clear, in SFL Theory, Fawcett's quantity group and quality group are both "reasonably handled in terms of an existing unit": the nominal group. Fawcett's quantity group over sixty is a nominal group with a Numerative as sub-modified Head, and Fawcett's quality group is a nominal group with an Epithet as sub-modified Head.


[3] To be clear, in SFL Theory also, the elements of these nominal group structures serve different functions: Numerative vs Epithet. Moreover, both can serve the same function at the rank above, Attribute, as in he was over sixty, he was quite clever.


In SFL Theory, groups are classified according to the clause functions they realise, not according to their internal structure. Halliday & Matthiessen (2014: 363):


Tuesday 1 December 2020

Fawcett's Criteria For Identifying Different Classes Of Syntactic Unit

Fawcett (2010: 195-6):
Since our topic in this book is syntax, I shall now re-express the semantic view taken in Section 10.2.1 in terms of concepts that are at the level of form. Then, since 'class of unit' is a key category in the present theory, I shall examine the extent to which the criterion for recognising 'classes' of unit proposed in "Categories" has been supported by other scholars.
In terms of criteria at the level of form, then, the different classes of syntactic unit that are recognised in the description of a language are to be identified by their internal structure, i.e., by the elements of structure of those units. This concept will be exemplified in the classes of unit in English described in Sections 10.2.3 to 10.2.12. For a fuller discussion of the concept of 'element of structure', see Section 10.5.⁶


Blogger Comments:

[1] To be clear, "the semantic view taken in Section 10.2.1" is the mutual determination of class of semantic unit and class of syntactic unit (p193):

… the class of a syntactic unit and of the semantic unit that it realises are mutually determined … each such class exists to express the specific array of meanings that are associated with each one of the major classes of entity in the semantics. … Each of these semantic units corresponds directly to one of the five major classes of syntactic unit that are recognised in the present syntax of English.

[2] To be clear, the validity of a theoretical proposition rests on reasoned argument, not on the extent to which it is supported by other scholars. This is another instance of the logical fallacy known as argumentum ad populum.

[3] To be clear, "the criterion for recognising classes in 'Categories' " is with reference to the structure of the unit above in the compositional rank scale.  Halliday (2002 [1960]: 49, 50):

The class is that grouping of members of a given unit which is defined by operation in the structure of the unit next above. … Class, like structure, is linked to unit: a class is always a class of (members of) a given unit: and the class–structure relation is constant – a class is always defined with reference to the structure of the unit next above, and structure with reference to classes of the unit next below. class is not a grouping of members of a given unit which are alike in their own structure. In other words, by reference to the rank scale, classes are derived “from above” (or “downwards”) and not “from below” (or “upwards”).

[4] To be clear, as can be seen from the quote immediately above, Fawcett's recognition criteria for classes of unit directly contradict the criteria used in the theory he is developing: Halliday's superseded Scale & Category Grammar. Whether or not this raises theoretical problems will be examined in future posts.